Tim Berners-Lee, August 2005
$Revision: 1.19 $ of $Date: 2010-02-19$
Status: An early draft of a semi-formal semantics of the N3 logical
properties.
Up to Design Issues
An RDF language for the Semantic Web
Notation 3 Logic
This article gives an operational semantics for Notation3 (N3) and
some RDF properties for expressing logic. These
properties, together with N3's extensions of RDF to include
variables and nested graphs, allow N3 to be used to express rules
in a web environment.
This is an informal semantics in that should be understandable by a
human being but is not a machine readable formal semantics.
This document is aimed at a logician wanting to a reference by
which to compare N3 Logic with other languages, and at the engineer
coding an implementation of N3 Logic and who wants to check the
detailed semantics.
These properties are not part of the N3 language, but are
properties which allow N3 to be used to express rules, and rules
which talk about the provenance of information, contents of
documents on the web, and so on. Just as OWL is expressed in
RDF by defining properties, so rules, queries, differences, and so
on can be expressed in RDF with the N3 extension to formulae.
The log: namespace has functions, which have built-in meaning
for CWM and other software.
See also:
The prefix log: is used below as shorthand for the
namespace <http://www.w3.org/2000/10/swap/log#>.
See the schema for a
summary.
Motivation
The motivation of the logic was to be useful as a tool in in open
web environment. The Web contains many sources of
information, with different characteristics and relationships to
any given reader. Whereas a closed system may be built
based on a single knowledge base of believed facts, an open
web-based system exists in an unbounded sea of interconnected
information resources. This requires that an agent be aware of the
provenance of information, and responsible for its
disposition. The language for use in this environment
typically requires the ability to express what document or message
said what, so the ability to quote subgraphs and match them against
variable graphs is essential. This quotation and
reference, with its inevitable possibility of direct or indirect
self-reference, if added directly to first order logic presents
problems such as paradox traps. To avoid this, N3 logic has
deliberately been kept to limited expressive power: it currently
contains no general first order negation. Negated forms
of many of the built-in functions are available, however.
A goal is that information, such as but not limited to rules, which
requires greater expressive power than the RDF graph, should be
sharable in the same way as RDF can be shared. This
means that one person should be able to express knowledge in N3 for
a certain purpose, and later independently someone else reuse that
knowledge for a different unforeseen purpose. As the
context of the later use is unknown, this prevents us from making
implicit closed assumptions about the total set of knowledge in the
system as a whole.
Further, we require that other users of N3 in the web can express
new knowledge without affecting systems we have already built.
This means that N3 must be fundamentally monotonic: the
addition of new information from elsewhere, while it might cause an
inconsistency by contradicting the old information (which would
have to be resolved before the combined system is used), the new
information cannot silently change the meaning of the original
knowledge.
The non-monotonicity of many existing systems follows from a form
of negation as failure in which a sentence is deemed false if it
not held within (or, derivable from) thecurrent knowledge base. It
is this concept of current knowledge base, which is a variable
quantity, and the ability to indirectly make reference to it which
causes the non-monotonicity. In N3Logic, while a current
knowledge base is a fine concept, there is no ability to make
reference to it implicitly in the negative. The
negation provided is the ability only for a specific given document
(or, essentially, some abstract formula) to objectively determine
whether or not it holds, or allows one to derive, a given
fact. This has been called Scoped Negation As Failure
(SNAF).
Formal syntax
The syntax of N3 is defined by the context-free
grammar This is available in machine-readable form in
Notation3
and RDF/XML.
The top-level production for an N3 document is
<http://www.w3.org/2000/10/swap/grammar/n3#document>.
In the semantics below we will consider these productions using
notation as follows.
Production |
N3 syntax examples |
notation below for instances |
symbol |
<foo#bar>
<http://example.com/> |
c d e f |
variable |
Any symbol quantified by @forAll or @forSome in the same or an
outer formula. |
x y z |
formula |
{ ...
} or an entire document |
F G H K |
set of universal variables of F |
@forAll :x,
:y. |
uvF |
set of existential variables of F |
@forSome :z,
:w. |
evF |
set of statements of F |
|
stF |
statement |
<#myCar>
<#color> "green". |
Fi or {s
p o} |
string |
"hello world" |
s |
integer |
34 |
i |
list |
( 1 2 ?x <a> ) |
L M |
Element i of list L |
|
Li
|
length of list |
|
|L| |
expression |
see grammar |
n m |
Set* |
{$ 1, 2, <a> $} |
S T
|
*The set syntax and semantics are not part of the current Notation3
language but are under consideraton.
Semantics
Note. The Semantics of
a generic RDF statement are not defined here. The
extensibility of RDF is deliberately such that a document may draw
on predicates from many sources. The statement {n c m}
expresses that the relationship denoted by c holds between the
things denoted by n and m. The meaning of
the statement {n c m} in general is defined by any
specification for c. The Architecture of the WWW specifies
informally how the curious can discover information about the
relation. It discusses how the architecture and management of the
WWW is such that a given social entity has jurisdiction over
certain symbols (though for example domain name ownership). This
philosophy and architecture is not discussed further
here. Here though we do define the semantics of certain
specific predicates which allow the expression of the
language. In analyzing the language the reader is
invited to consider statements of unknown meaning ground
facts. N3Logic defines the semantics of certain
properties. Clearly a system which recognizes further logical
predicates, beyond those defined here, whose meaning introduces
greater logical expressiveness would change the properties of the
logic.
Simplifications
N3 has a number of types of shortcut syntax and syntactic sugar.
For simplicity, in this article we consider a
language simpler the full N3 syntax referenced above though
just as expressive, in that we ignore most syntactic sugar. The
following simplifications are made.
We ignore syntactic sugar of comma and semicolon as shorthand
notations. That is, we consider a simpler language in which
any such syntax has been expanded out. Loosely:
A sentence of the form |
becomes two sentences |
subject stuff ;
morestuff . |
subject stuff .
subject morestuff
. |
subject predicate stuff , object . |
subject predicate stuff subject
predicate object . |
For those familiar with N3, the other simplifications in the
language considered here are as follows.
- prefixes have been expanded and all qualified names
replaced with symbols using full URIs between angle brackets.
- The path syntax which uses "!" and "^" is
assumed expanded into its equivalent blank node form;
- The "is ... of " backwards construction has been replaced by
the equivalent forwards direction syntax.
- The "=" syntax is not used as shorthand for owl:sameAs. In
fact, we use = here in the text for value equality.
- @keywords is not used
- The @a shorthand for rdf:type is replaced with a
direct use of the full URI symbol for rdf:type
- all ?x forms are replaced with explicit universal
quantification in the enclosing parent of the current formula.
Notation3 has explicitly quantified existential variables as well
as blank nodes. The description below does not mention
blank nodes, although they are very close in semantics to
existentially quantified variables. We consider for now
a simpler language in which blank nodes have been replaced by
explicitly named variables existentially quantified in
the same formula.
We have only included strings and integers, rather than the whole
set of RDF types an user-defined types.
These simplifications will not deter us from using N3 shorthand in
examples where it makes them more readable, so the reader is
assumed familiar with them.
Defining N3 Entailment
The RDF specification defines a very weak form of entailment, known
as RDF entailment or simple entailment. He we define the
equivalent very simple N3-entailment. This does not provide us with
useful powers of inference: it is almost textual inclusion, but
just has conjunction elimination (statement removal) ,
universal elimination, existential introduction and variable
renaming. Most of this is quite traditional. The
only thing to distinguish N3 Logic from typical logics is the
Formula, which allows N3 sentences to make statements about N3
sentences. The following details are included for
completeness and may be skipped.
Substitution
Substitution is defined to
recursively apply inside compound terms, as is
usual. Note only that substitution does descend into
compund terms, while substitution of owl:sameAs, discussed later,
does not.
We define a substitution operator
σx/m
which replaces occurrences of the variable x. with the expression m. For
compound terms, substitution of a compound term (list,
formula or set) is performed by performing substitution of
each component, recursively.
Abbreviating the substitution σx/m as σ , we define
substitution operator as usual:
σx = m
(x is replaced by
m)
σy = y (y not
equal to x)
σa = a (symbols and literals are
unchanged)
σi = i
σs = s
σ( a b ... c ) = ( σa σb ... σc
)
(substitution goes into compound terms)
σ{$ a, b, ... c $} = {$ σa,
σb, ... σc $}
uv σF = σ uvF
ev σF = σ evF
st σF = σ stF
In general a substitution operator is the sequential application of
single substitutions:
σ = σx1/m1σx2/m2σx2/m2 ...
σxn/mn
Value equality
Value equality between terms is
defined in an ordinary way, compatible with RDF.
For concepts which exist in RDF, we use RDF equality. This is
RDF node equality. These atomic concepts have a simple form
of equality.
For lists, equality is defined as a pairwise matching.
For sets, equality is defined as a mapping between equal terms
existing in each direction.
For formulae, equality F = G is defined as a
substitution σ existing mapping variables to variables.
(Note that as here RDF Blank Nodes are considered as
existential variables, the substitution will map b-nodes to
b-nodes.)
The table below is a summary for completeness.
Production |
Equality |
symbol |
uri is equal unicode string |
variable |
variable name is equal unicode string |
formula |
F = G iff |stF| = |stG| and there is some
substitution σ such that (∀i . ∃j . σFi = σGj. ) |
statement |
Subjects are equal, predicates are equal, and objects are
equal |
string |
equal unicode string |
integer |
equal integer |
list L = M |
|L| = |M| &
(∀i .
Li = Mi ) |
set S = T |
(∀i
. ∃j .
Si = Tj. ) &
(∀i
. ∃j .
Si = Tj. ) |
formula F = G |
∃σ. σ F = σ G |
unicode string |
Unicode strings should be in canonical form. They are equal if
the corresponding characters have numerically equal code
points. |
Conjunction
N3, like RDF, has an implied
conjunction, with its normal properties, between the statements of
a formula.
The semantics of a formula which has no quantifiers (@forAll or
@forSome) are the conjunction of the semantics of the statements of
which it is composed.
We define the conjunction elimination operator ce(i) of removing
the statement Fi from
formula F. By the conventional semantics of conjunction, the
ce(i) operator is truth-preserving. If you take a formula and
remove a statement from it it is still true.
CE: From F follows ce(i)
F
Existential quantification
Existential quantifiers and
Universal quantifiers have the usual qualities
Any formula, including the root
formula which matches the "document" production of the
grammar, may have a set of existential variables indicated by
an @forSome
declaration. This indicates that, where the formula is
considered true, it is true for at least one substitution mapping
the existential variables onto non-variables.
As usual, we define a truth-preserving Existential
Introduction operator on formulae, that of introducing an
existentially quantified variable in place of any term. The
operation ei(x, n) is defined as
- Creation of a new variable x which occurs nowhere else
- The application of σx/n to F
- The addition ofx
to evF.
EI: From F follows ei(x,n) F
for any x not
occurring anywhere else
Universal quantification
Any formula, (including the root formula), may have a set of
universal variables. These are indicated by
@forAll
declarations. The scope of the @forAll is outside the
scope of any @forSome.
If both universal and existential quantification are specified
for the same context, then the scope of the universal
quantification is outside the scope of the existentials:
{ @forAll <#h>. @forSome <#g>. <#g> <#loves> <#h> }.
means
∀<#h> ( ∃<#g> ((
<#g>
<#loves> <#h> ))
The semantics of @forAll is that for any substitution σ
= subst(x, n) where
x member of uvF, if F is true then σF
is also true. Any @forAll declaration may also be removed,
preserving truth. Combining these, we define a
truth-preserving operation ue(x, n) such that
ue(x, n) F is formed by
- Removal of x from evF
- Application of subst(x, n)
We have the axiom of universal elimination
UE: From F follows
ue(x, n) F for all x in evF
As the actual variable used in a formula is quite irrelevant to its
semantics, the operation of replacing that variable with another
one not used elsewhere within the formula is
truth-preserving.
Variable renaming
We define the operation of variable renaming vr(x,y) on F when x is a member of uvF or
is a member of evF.
VR: From F follows vr(x, y) F where
x is in uvF or evF
and y does not occur in
F
Occurrence in F is defined recursively in the same way as
substitution: x
occurs in F iff σx/nF is not equal to F for
arbitrary n.
Union of formulae
The union H = F∪G of two formulae F and G is formed, as
usual, as follows.
A variable renaming operator is applied to G such that the
resulting formula G' has no variables which occur un-quantified or
differently quantified or existentially quantified in F, and
vice-versa. (F and G' may share universal variables).ied
or existentially quantified in F, and vice-ver
F∪G is then defined by:
st(F∪G) = stF ∪ st G' ; ev(F∪G)
= evF ∪ evG' ; uv(F∪G) =
uvF ∪ uv G'
N3 entailment
The operators conjunction elimination, existential elimination,
universal introduction and variable renaming are truth
preserving. We define an N3 entailment operator (τ)
as any operator which is the successive application of any
sequence (possibly empty) of such operators. We say a
formula F n3-entails a formula τ F. By a
combination of SE, EI, UE and VR, τ F
logically follows from F.
Note. RDF Graph is a
subclass of N3 formula. If F and G are RDF graphs, only CI
and EI apply and n3-entailment reduces to simple entailment
from RDF Semantics. (@@check for any RDF weirdnesses)
We have now defined this simple form of N3-entailment,
which amounts to little more than textual inclusion in one
expression of a subset of another. We have not defined
the normal collection of implication, disjunction and negation
which first order logic, as N3logic does provide for first order
negation. We have, in the process, defined a
substitution operation which we can now use to define implication,
which allows us to express rules.
Logic properties and built-in functions
We now define the semantics of N3 statements whose predicate is one
of a small set of logic properties. These are statements
whose truth can be established by performing calculations, or by
accessing the web.
One of our objectives was to make it possible to make statements
about, and to query, other statements such as the contents of data
in information resources on the web. We have, in formulae,
the ability to represent such sets of statements. Now,
to allow statements about them, we take some of the relationships
we have defined and give them URIs so that these statements and
queries can be written in N3.
While the properties we introduced can be used simply as ground
facts in a database, is very useful to take advantage of the
fact that in fact they can be calculated. In some cases, the
truth or falsehood of a binary relation can be calculated; in
others, the relationship is a function so one argument (subject or
object of the statement) can be calculated from the other.
We now show how such properties are defined, and give examples of
how an inference system can use them. A motivation here
is to do for logical information what RDF did for data: to provide
a common data model and a common syntax, so that extensions of the
language are made simply by defining new terms in an
ontology. Declarative programing languages like
scheme[@@] of course do this. However, they differ in their
choice of pairs rather than the RDF binary relational model for
data, and lack the use of universal identifiers as
symbols. The goal with N3 was to make a
minimal extension to the RDF data model, so that the
same language could be used for logic and data, which in practice
are mixed as a colloidal solution in many real applications.
Calculated entailment
We introduce also a set of properties whose truth may be evaluated
directly by machine. We call these "built-in"
functions. The implementation as built-in functions
is not in general required for any implementation of the
N3 language, as they can always soundly be treated as ground
facts. However, their usefulness derives from their
implementation. We say that for example { 1
math:negation -1 } is entailed by
calculation. Like other RDF properties, the
set is designed to be extensible, as others can use URIs for new
functions. A much larger set of such properties is described for
example in the CWM bultt-ins list, and the semantics of those
are not described here.
When the truth of a statement can be deduced because its predicate
is a built-in function, then we call the derivation of the
statement from no other evidence calculated entailment.
We now define a small set of such properties which provide the
power of N3 logic for inference on the web.
log:includes
If a formula G n3-entails another formula F, this is
expressed in N3 logic as
F log:includes
G.
Note. In deference to the
fact that RDF treats lists not as terms but as things constructed
from first and rest pairs, we can view formulae which include lists
as including rdf:first and rdf:rest statements. The effect on
inclusion is that two other entailment operations are added: the
addition of any statement of the form L rdf:first
nwhere n is the first
element of L, or L rdf:rest K where K is list forming the remaining
non-first elements of L. This is not essential to a further
understanding of the logic, nor to the operation of a system which
does not contain any explicit mention of the terms rdf:first or
rdf:rest.
For the discussion of n3-entailment, clearly:
From F and F log:includes G
logically follows G
This can be calculated, because it is a mathematical operation on
two compound terms. It is typically used in a query to test
the contents of a formula. Below we will show how it can be
used in the antecedent of a rule.
log:notIncludes
We write of formulae F and G: F log:notIncludes G if it is
not the case that G
n3-entails F.
As a form of negation, log:notincludes is completely monotonic.
It can be evaluated by a mathematical calculation on the
value of the two terms: no other knowledge gained can influence the
result. This is the scoped
negation as failure mentioned in the introduction.
This is not a non-monotonic negation as failure.
Note on computation: To
ascertain whether G n3-entails F in the worst case involves
checking for all possible n3-entailment transformations which
are combinations of the variables which occur in G. This operation
may be tedious: it is strictly graph isomorphism complete.
However the use of symbols rather than variables for a good
proportion of nodes makes it much more tractable for practical
graphs. The ethos that it is a good idea to give name
things with URIs (symbols in N3) is a basic meme of web
architecture [AWWW]. It has direct practical application
in the calculation of n3-entailment, as comparison of graphs whose
nodes are labelled is much faster (of order n log
(n)))
The log:implies property relates two formulae, expressing
implication. The shorthand notation for log:implies is
=>
. A statement using log:implies, unlike log:includes,
cannot be calculated. It is not a built-in function, but
the predicate which allows the expression of a rule.
The semantics of implication are
standard, but we elaborate them now for
completeness.
F log:implies G is true if and only if when the formula F is true
then also G is true.
MP: From F and F
=> G follows G
A statement in formula H is of the form F=>G can be
considered as rule, in which case, the subject F is the premise
(antecedent) of the rule, and the object G is the consequent.
Implication is normally used within a formula with universally
quantified variables.
For example, universal quantifiers
are used with a rule in H as follows. Here H is
the formula containing the rules, and K the formula upon which the
rules are applied, which we can call the knowledge base.
If F => G is in H, and then for every σ which is
a transformation composed of universal eliminations of variables
universally quantified in H, then it also follows that
σF => σG. Therefore, for every σ such
that K includes σF, σG follows from
K.
In the particular case that H and K are both the knowledge base, or
formula believed true at the top level, then
GMP: From F => G
and σF follows σG
if σ is a transformation composed of
universal eliminations of variables universally quantified at the
top level.
Filtering
When a knowledge base (formula) contains a lot of information, one
way to filter off a subset is to run a set of rules on the
knowledge base, and take only the new data which is generated by
the rules. This is the filter operation.
When you apply rules to a knowledge base, the filter result of rules in H applied to
K is the union of all σG for every statement F
=> G which is in H, for every σ which s a
transformation composed of universal eliminations of variables
universally quantified in H such that K includes σF.
Repeated application of rules
When rules are added back repeatedly into the same knowledge
base, in order to prevent the unnecessary extra growth of the
knowledge base, before adding σG to it, there is a
check to see whether the H already includes σG, and if
it does, the adding of σG is skipped.
Let the result of rules in H applied to K,
ρHK, be the union of K with
all σG for every statement F => G which is in
H, for every σ which is a transformation
composed of universal eliminations of variables universally
quantified in H, such that K includes σF, and K does not
n3-entail σG.
Note. This form of rule allows
existentials in the consequent: it is not datalog. It is
is clearly possible in a forward-chaining reasoner to generate an
unbounded set of conclusions with rules of the form (using
shorthand)
{ ?x a :Person
} => { ?x :mother [ a :Person] }.
While this is a trap for the
unwary user of a forward-chaining reasoner, it was found to be
essential in general to be able to generate arbitrary RDF
containing blank nodes, for example when translating information
from one ontology into another.
Consider the repeated application of rules in H to K,
ρiHK. If there
are no existentially quantified variables in the consequents of any
of the rules in H, then this is like datalog, and there will be
some threshold n above
which no more data is added, and there is a closure:
ρiHK =
ρnHK for all
i>n. In fact in many practical
applications even with the datalog constraint removed, there is
also a closure. This ρ∞HK is
the result of running a forward-chaining reasoner on H and K.
Rule Inference on the knowledge base
In the case in which rules are in the same formula as the data, the
single rule operation can be written ρKK, and
the closure under rule application
ρ∞KK
Cwm note: the --rules command line
option calculates ρKK,
and the --think calculates ρ∞KK.
The --filter=H calculates the filter result of H on the
knowledge base.
Examples
Here a simple rule uses log:implies.
@prefix log: <http://www.w3.org/2000/10/swap/log#>.
@keywords.
@forAll x, y, z. {x parent y. y sister z} log:implies {x aunt z}
This N3 formula has three universally quantified variables and
one statement. The subject of the statement,
{x parent y. y sister z}
is the antecedent of the rule and the object,
{x aunt z}
is the conclusion. Given data
Joe parent Alan.
Alan sister Susie.
a rule engine would conclude
Joe aunt Susie.
As a second example, we use a rule which looks inside a
formula:
@forAll x, y, z.
{ x wrote y.
y log:includes {z weather w}.
x livesIn z
} log:implies {
Boston weather y
}.
Here the rule fires when x is bound to a symbol denoting some
person who is the author of a formula y, when the formula makes a
statement about the weather in (presumably some place) z, and x's
home is z. That is, we believe statements about the
weather at a place only from people who live there. Given the
data
Bob livesIn Boston.
Bob wrote { Boston weather sunny }.
Alice livesIn Adelaide.
Alice wrote { Boston weather cold }.
a valid inference would be
Boston weather sunny.
log:supports
We say that F log:supports G if there is some sequence of
rule inference and/or calculated entailment and/or n3
entailment operators which when applied to F produce G.
log:conclusion
The log:conclusion property expresses the relationship between a
formula and its deductive closure under operations of
n3-entailment, rule entailment and calculated entailment.
As noticed above, there are circumstances when this will not be
finite.
log:conclusion is the transitive closure of log:supports.
log:supports can be written in terms of log:conclusion and
log:includes.
{ ?x log:supports ?y } if and only dan { ?x
log:conclusion [ log:includes ?y ]}
However, log:supports may be evaluated in many cases without
evaluating log:conclusion: one can determine whether y can be
derived from x in many ways, such as backward chaining, without
necessarily having to evaluate the (possibly infinite) deductive
closure.
Now we have a system which has the capacity to do inference using
rules, and to operate on formulae. However, it operates
in a vacuum. In fact, our goal is that the system should
operate in the context of the web.
Involving the Web
We therefore expose the web as a mapping between URIs and the
information returned when such a URI is dereferenced, using
appropriate protocols. In N3, the information
resource is identified by a symbol, which is in fact is its URI. In
N3, information is represented in formulae, so we represent the
information retrieved as a formula.
Not all information on the web is, of course in N3. However the
architecture we design is that N3 should here be the interlingua.
Therefore, from the point of view of this system, the semantics of
a document is exactly what can be expressed in N3, no more and no
less.
log:semantics**
c log:semantics F is true iff c is a document whose
logical semantics expressed in N3 is the formula F.
The relation between a document and the logical expression which
represents its meaning expressed as N3. The
Architecture of the World Wide Web [AWWW] defines algorithms by
which a machine can determine representations of
document given its symbol (URI). For a
representation in N3, this is the formula which corresponds to the
document production of the
grammar. For a representation in RDF/XML it
is the formula which is the entire graph parsed. For any
other languages, it may be calculated in as much a
specification exists which defines the equivalent N3 semantics for
files in that language.
On the meaning of N3 formula
This is not of course the semantics of the document in any
absolute sense. It is the semantics expressed in
N3. In turn, the full semantics of an N3 formula are
grounded, in the definitions of the properties and classes
used by the formula. In the HTTP space in which
URIs are minted by an authority, definitive information about those
definitions may be found by dereferencing the URIs. This
information may be in natural language, in some machine-processable
logic, or a mixture. Two patterns are important for the
semantic web.
One is the grounding of properties and classes by defining them
in natural language. Natural language, of course, is not
capable of giving an absolute meaning to anything in theory, but in
practice a well written document, carefully written by a group of
people achieves a precision of definition which is quite sufficient
for the community to be able to exchange data using the terms
concerned. The other pattern is the raft-like definition
of terms in terms of related neighboring ontologies.
@@@@ A full discussion of the grounding of meaning in a
web of such definitions is beyond the scope of this
article. Here we define only the operation semantics of
a system using N3.
@@@@ Edited up to here
The log:semantics of an N3 document is the formula achieved by
parsing representation of the document.
(Cwm note: Cwm knows how to go get a document and parse N3 and
RDF/XML , in order to evaluate this. )
Other languages for web documents may be defined whose N3
semantics are therefore also calculable, and so they could be added
in due course.
See for example [GRDDL], [RDF/A], etc
However, for the purpose of the analysis of the language, it is
a convenient to consider the semantic web simply as a binary
1:1 relation between a subset of symbols and formulae.
For a document in Notation3, log:semantics is the
log:parsedAsN3 of the log:contents of the document.
log:says
log:says is defined by:
F log:says G iff ∃ H .
F log:semantics
H and H log:includes G
In other words, loosely a document says something if a
representation of it in the sense of the Architecture of the World
Wide Web [AWWW] N3-entails it.
The semantics of log:says are similar to that of says in
[PCA].
Miscellaneous
log:Truth
This is a class of true formulae.
From { F rdf:type log:Truth } follows
F
The cwm engine will process rules in the (indirectly
command-line specified) formula or any formula which that declares
to be a Truth.
The dereifier will output any described formulae which are
described as being in the class Truth.
This class is not at all central to the logic.
Working with OWL
@@ Summary
- owl:sameAs considered the same as N3 value equality for data
values. Axioms of equality. log:equalTo and
log:notEqualTo compared with owl:SameAs. Compare math
and string equality, and SPARQL equality.
- Operating in equality-aware mode.
- No attempt at connecting OWL DL language with the N3
logic.
- Use of functional properties of a datatype conflicting with OWL
DL.
Conclusion
The semantics of N3 have been defined, as have some built-in
operator properties which add logical inference using rules to the
language, and allow rules to define inference which can be drawn
from specific web documents on the web, as a function of other
information about those documents.
The language has been found to have some useful practical
properties. The separation between the Notation3
extensions to RDF and the logic properties has allowed N3 by itself
to be used in many other applications directly, and to be used with
other properties to provide other functionality such as the
expression of patches (updates) [Diff].
The use of log:notIncludes to allow default reasoning without
non-monotonic behavior achieves a design goal for distributed rule
systems.
**[Footnote: Philosophers may be distracted here into worrying
about the meaning of meaning. At least we didn't call this function
"meaning"! In as much as N3 is used as an interlingua for
interoperability for different systems, this for an N3 based system
is the meaning expressed by a document. One reviewer was
aghast at the definition of semantics as being that of retrieval of
a representation, its parsing and assimilation in terms of the
local common logical framework. I suspect however that the meaning
of the paper to the reviewer could be considered quite equivalently
the result of the process of retrieval of a
representation of the paper, its parsing by the review, and its
assimilation in terms of the reviewer's local logical framework: a
similar though perhaps imperfect process.
Of course, the semantics of many documents are not expressible in
logics at all, and many in logic but not in N3. However, we are
building a system for which a prime goal is the reading and
investigation of machine-readable documents on the web. We use the
URI log:semantics for this function and apologize for any heartache
it may cause.]
F = G iff |stF| =
|stG| and there is some substitution σ such
that (∀i
. ∃j .
σFi =
σGj. )
formatting XHTML 1 with nvu
yes, discuss notational
abbreviation, but not abstract syntax
hmm... are log:includes,
log:implies and such predicates? relations? operators?
properties?
To do: describe the syntactic
sugar transformations formally to close the loop.